Dr. Pushpa Rani Prasad, a Commissioned acting Principal working at S.P. Mahila College, Dumka, Jharkhand (India) writing in both English and Hindi. She is a pioneer of modern vision and her voice for modern Indian women is miracle and outstanding.
Dr. Pushpa Rani Prasad |
Abstract
The attempt to put knowledge on certain foundation is
historically associated with the philosophy of Descartes. The most important question that has recurred
most frequently regarding Descartes’ dictum ‘Cogito,
ergo sum’ is that whether the proposition ‘I think, therefore I am’ is or
is not an inference. According to Descartes, by saying cogito, ergo sum, he does not logically (syllogistically) deduce sum from cogito but rather perceives intuitively, the self-evidence of sum. But, there are several passages in
the ‘Discourse and Principles’ that
cause problems for the above view of Descartes. Philosophers differ on the
exact relation of cogito to sum. Bernard Williams has defended the
view that it is a kind of inference, though not syllogistic in form. On the
other hand, in a recent paper Jaakko Hintikka has expressed the view that the
word cogito serves to express the
performatory character of Descartes’ insight. In this article, I have also
examined Peter Markie’s view that it is self-evident Intuition/Immediate
Inference Interpretation. In this article, I have tried to clear up the
relation of cogito to sum.
The Relation of Cogito to Sum
Descartes employed methodic doubt with a view to discovering
whether there was any indubitable truth. Though he regarded mathematics as the
paradigm of knowledge, he knew that its ‘a
priori truths’ are not indubitable because it was possible that a malignant
demon should deceive him even with respect to those matters of which he was
most certain. But he found that there was one proposition which was capable of
escaping the demon’s reach. This was his famous dictum the ‘Cogito, Ergo Sum’ – ‘I think, therefore I am’.
Descartes writes:
“But I have convinced myself that there
is absolutely nothing in the world, no sky, no earth, no minds, no bodies. Does
it now follow that I too do not exist? No, if I convinced myself of something
then I certainly existed. But there is a deceiver of supreme power and cunning
who is deliberately and constantly deceiving me; and let him deceive me as much
as he can, he will never bring it about that I am nothing so long as I think
and that I am something. So after considering everything very thoroughly, I must
finally conclude that this proposition, I am, I exist, is necessarily true
whenever it is put forward by me or conceived in my mind.”1
At first sight, the cogito
certainly seems to be an inference. Descartes’ dictum really express an
inference is suggested by the particle ergo. In many respects it seems
plausible to think that it does express a logical inference. Its logical form seems
quite easy to define. In the sentence ‘I think’, an individual receives an
attribute; for a modern logician it is therefore of the form “B(a)”. In the
sentence ‘I am’ or ‘I exist’ the same individual is said to exist. Such type of
views has been expressed by many philosophers. Gassendi claimed that ‘ambulo, ergo sum’, ‘ I walk, therefore
I am’, is as good an inference as cogito,
ergo sum.
In his reply to Gassendi, Descartes denies that ambulo, ergo sum is comparable with ‘cogito, ergo sum’. The reasons he gave
are not very clear. Descartes’ remark is perhaps that although the inferences ‘ambulo, ergo sum’ and ‘cogito, ergo sum’ are parallel, their
premises are essentially different. Ambulo
is not an indubitable premise in the way cogito
may be claimed to be.
In many passages Descartes seems to deny that by saying cogito, ergo sum he does logically
(syllogistically) deduce sum from cogito.
According to him, “he rather perceives intuitively (by a single act mental
vision) the self-evidence of sum”.
Descartes writes:
“When someone says ‘I think, therefore
I am’, he does not deduce his existence from his thinking by means of a
syllogism, but, by the mind’s simple act of inspection, sees it something that
is self-evident. This is apparent from the fact that, if he deduced it by means
of a syllogism, he would first have had to know the major premise, “Everything
that thinks is or exists”. But that, on the contrary, has been learned from the
individuals awareness of himself – that he cannot be thinking unless he exists.
For it is the nature of our mind to form general propositions from knowledge of
particulars”.2
Jaakko Hintikka is of the view that the relation of the two
parts of the ‘cogito, ergo sum’
cannot be a logical inference in the ordinary sense of the word. According to
him, in Descartes’ argument the relation of cogito
to sum is not that of premise to a
conclusion. He says that, “their relation is rather comparable with that of a
process to its product. The indubitability of my own existence results from my
thinking of it almost as the sound of music results from playing it or light in
the sense of illumination (lux)
results from the presence of a source of light (lumen)3. Regarding the function of the word cogito in Descartes’ sentence as well as
his motives in employing it, Hintikka says that, “it serves to express the
performatory character of Descartes’ insight; it refers to the “performance”
(to the act of thinking) through, which the sentence ‘I exist’ may be said to verify
itself. For this reason, it has a most important function in Descartes’
sentence. It cannot be replaced by any arbitrary verb. The performance (act)
through which the existential self-verifiability is manifested cannot be any
arbitrary human activity, contrary to what Gassendi claimed. It cannot be an
act of walking or an act of seeing”.4
Peter Markie is of the view that the answer to this problem
is that:
“Descartes intuits the self-evident
proposition that he thinks and simultaneously infers that he exists. His
knowledge that he thinks is intuitive in the primary sense of being
self-evident and entirely non-inferential; his knowledge that he exists is intuitive
in the extended sense of being immediately inferred from the simultaneously intuited
premise that he thinks”.5
Markie has referred to many statements
of Descartes, which support this interpretation. Descartes presents intuition
and deduction as his only sources of certainty in the Regulae. According
to Descartes, deduction is the inference of something as following necessarily
from some other propositions with certainty. Intuition is the faculty by which
we gain the initial certainties that make deduction possible. Intuition is
distinguished from deduction by the fact that it does not involve a movement of
thought through a series of inferences and by its immediate self-evidence.
According to Descartes, when we
immediately infer a conclusion from an intuited self-evident premise, we are
not aware of any movement of thought through series of premises, so we may
describe our knowledge of the conclusion as intuitive. No extended series of
intuitions lead us to the conclusion, there is just one mental act in which the
self-evident premise is intuited and the immediate conclusion is drawn.
Descartes’ remarks in the Discourse and Principles further support this interpretation. In Discourse Descartes says, “And observing
that this truth ‘I am thinking therefore I exist’ was so firm and sure that all
the most extravagant suppositions of the skeptics were incapable of shaking it,
I decided that I could accept without scruple as the first principle of the
philosophy I was seeking”.6
In the Principles
Descartes writes:
“For
it is a contradiction to suppose that what thinks does not, at the very time it
is thinking, exist. Accordingly, this piece of knowledge – I am thinking; therefore,
I exist – is the first and most certain of all to occur to anyone who philosophizes
in an orderly way”.7
In each passage, Descartes presents his immediate inference
from his thought to his existence as a single piece of knowledge, it is the
first principle of his philosophy. His point seems to be that in one act of
intuition, he grasps the premise and immediately infers the conclusion.
Peter Markie has called this interpretation “The
self-evident Intuition/Immediate inference interpretation”. But, Descartes’
arguments in some passages cause problems for the above interpretation. In one
of the passages in the Principles,
Descartes says that prior to knowing that he thinks and therefore he exists, he
must know, not only what thought, existence and certainty are, but also the
general proposition that it is impossible for what thinks not to exist. His
point seems to be that his inference from his thought to his existence uses the
general proposition as a suppressed premise. It is not, ‘I am thinking,
therefore I exist’, it is ‘I am thinking and whatever is thinking must exist,
therefore I exist’.
But
in his comment to Mersenne in Second
Replies, Descartes explicitly denies that his inference from his thought to
existence is a syllogism using the general premise that whatever thinks must
exist. He repeats the same point in response to one of Gassendi’s objections.
If we modify our interpretation so that Descartes’ inference
uses the general premise that whatever thinks must exist, we shall be in
conflict with his replies to Mersenne and Gassendi, but if we do not modify our
interpretation in this way, how are we to account for his claim in the Principles, that prior to knowing that
we think and therefore exist, we must know whatever thinks must exist.
There are several passages that conflict with the
self-evident Intuition/Immediate Inference Interpretation. Peter Markie
suggests that the Self-evident Intuition/Immediate Inference interpretation can
be modified to account for some, though not all, of the problematic passages.
To develop the new interpretation, he has examined two basic concepts of
Descartes' epistemology, his concept of certainty and his concept of reasonable
belief. Descartes' epistemology contains two degrees of epistemic appraisal.
One is the top standard of certainty and the other is a lesser degree of
justification, which Descartes describes as highly probable or very reasonable
belief. All the beliefs that meet the demands of certainty for him, such as his
belief about his thought and existence in the Second Meditation, are also very reasonable, but some of his very
reasonable beliefs, such as his sensory evidenced beliefs about the external
world in the First Meditation, are
not certain for him. Which degree of epistemic appraisal a belief meets is
determined by his evidence for the belief. The sensory evidence Descartes has
for his external world beliefs in the First
Meditation makes those beliefs very reasonable but not certain. The
evidence Descartes has for his belief in the existence in the Second Meditation makes that belief both
very reasonable and certain. When a belief is self-evident, Descartes' evidence
for it consists of his act of clearly and distinctly perceiving it. When a
belief is not self-evident, Descartes' evidence for it consists of those belief
that constitute his reason for believing it. The difference between what is
merely very reasonable and what is certain is that Descartes has slight reason
to doubt the former. A hypothesis gives Descartes a reason to doubt one of his
beliefs just when it is a possibility he has not ruled out and it indicates how
his belief might be false despite his evidence. The hypothesis that he is
dreaming and that some God deceives him are possibilities he has· not ruled out
in the First Meditation and they
indicate how his very reasonable beliefs about the external world might be
false despite his sensory evidence for them.
In Peter Markie’s view, relative to these points we can
better understand Descartes' claim to certainty about his thought and
existence. Descartes' claim has two parts:
(i) He has evidence for these beliefs that makes them very
reasonable.
(ii) That evidence resists even the slightest, most exaggerated
reasons for doubt, so that his beliefs are certainties.
In the light of above points, the Self-Evident Intuition/Immediate
Inference Interpretation may be modified. The first thing Descartes must do is
explain what makes his beliefs in his thought and existence very reasonable.
This is where his frequent appeals to clear and distinct perception and an
immediate inference from his thought to existence come into play. Descartes
takes his belief in his thought to be very reasonable because the proposition
that he thinks is a self-evident one he clearly and distinctly perceives to be
true. His act of clear and distinct perception is the "evidence" that
makes his belief that he thinks very reasonable. The same may be said of his
other beliefs about his mental state. His belief in the existence is very
reasonable, because he immediately infers it from a very reasonable belief
about his mental state.
Yet, what makes these beliefs so reasonable as to be certain?
Descartes' answer is that he has no reason to doubt them. Now his observation
about how reasons for doubt just affirm his thought and existence comes into
play. In Second Meditation Descartes
says the Deceptive God Hypothesis and Dream Hypothesis do not give him a reason
to doubt his beliefs that he thinks and exists; for they entails them and so
fails to indicate how they might be false despite his clear and distinct
perception.
If we modify our interpretation in the above way Descartes’
claim appears to be consistent.
Now we will see how the above modified interpretation deals
with the passages that cause problems for the initial one. Our modified
interpretation easily avoids one of the problems we have examined. Our initial
interpretation is inconsistent with Descartes' claim, in the Meditations and Replies, that some clear
and distinct perceptions, specifically ones of very simple mathematical truths,
are made doubtful by the Deceptive God Hypothesis. Our modified interpretation
is consistent with Descartes' claim. It says all clear and distinct perceptions
are very reasonable and only those that concern our thought and existence are
certain. The difference between the certain clear and distinct perceptions and
the merely very reasonable ones is that the former resist reasons for doubt
like Deceptive God Hypotheses. Such reasons for doubt do not indicate how our
beliefs in our thought and existence might be false despite the clear and
distinct perceptions that support them.
Another problem concerns whether Descartes' inference from
his thought to his existence is immediate or a syllogism. We have seen a
passage in the Principles insists on
the importance of a prior knowledge of the general principle that whatever
thinks must exist. The way to account for this passage is to pay close
attention to what Descartes says he must know prior to knowing his thought and
existence. He must know that what thinks must exist, and he must also know what
knowledge, thought, existence and certainty are. His point surely is not that
all this information must be added to his inference from thought to existence
to bridge the gap between his initial premise and his conclusion. He does not
need to add definitions of thought, existence and certainty to his argument to
get from "I think" to "I exist." His point is this: he must
have some of this information to understand the propositions that he thinks and
that he exists and the rest to understand his account of why they are certain
for him. He cannot understand the propositions, unless he knows what thought
and existence are. He cannot understand his account of why they are certain for
him unless he knows what certainty is. He cannot understand his account of why
they are certain unless he knows that what thinks must exist; for part of his account
is that his belief that he thinks immediately entails, and so makes reasonable,
his belief that he exists. Descartes does not offer the general principle that
what thinks must exist as a suppressed premise in his inference from his
thought to his existence. He offers it as something he must know to understand
why his thought and existence are certain for him. Moreover, it is sufficient
that this general principle is reasonable for Descartes; it need not be
certain. When Descartes claims to be certain of his thought and existence in
the Second Meditation, he does not
offer that claim to certainty - I am certain about my thoughts and existence as
a certainty. He presents it and his explanation of why it is true as reasonable
beliefs about his epistemic state.
Thus, we see that Peter Markie’s modified version of the
self-evident Intuition/Immediate Inference Interpretation avoids the textual
problems with the initial version. The above arguments clearly show that the
proposition Cogito, Ergo Sum is not
an inference.
Conclusion
Descartes’ claim to certainty about his thought and
existence is central to his general program in epistemology. He wants to answer
skepticism, and he wants to do so within foundationalism, the view that all our
knowledge begins with some self-evident beliefs which are not evidenced by any
others but yet provide our justification for all the rest we know. His claim to
certainty about his thought and existence is the initial move in his attempt to
define the set of self-evident beliefs. Descartes also thinks that his claim to
certainty of his thought and existence plays an important role in his
metaphysics. He says that the real value of his dictum ‘I think, therefore I
am’ is that it can be used to establish that this ‘I which is thinking is an
immaterial substance with no bodily element’. This is a continuing theme in
Descartes’ philosophy.
But we find that there are some underlying philosophical
issues that Descartes leaves. Philosophers have objected to his account of how
he gains the very reasonable belief that he thinks to begin with. He says he
clearly and distinctly perceives that he thinks. His concept of clear and
distinct perception is the least clear and distinct concept in philosophy. He
never adequately explains what this mental vision is or why apprehending a
proposition by it is sufficient to make belief in the proposition very
reasonable. Descartes leaves us wondering exactly how our beliefs about our
mental state and existence become reasonable. Descartes is open to a criticism
nicely stated by A.J. Ayer.
“What Descartes thought that he had
shown was that the statements that he was conscious, and that he existed, were
somehow privileged, that, for him at least, they were evidently true in a way
which distinguished them from any other statements of fact. But this by no
means follows from his argument. His argument does not prove that he, or
anyone, knows anything. It simply makes the logical point that one sort of
statement follows from another”.8
Descartes needs both parts of his explanation of his
certainty. He needs an account of what makes his beliefs in his thought and
existence very reasonable and an account of why those reasonable beliefs resist
every reason for doubt. It may be said in Descartes favour that the issues
which he has raised makes his position interesting and important. Thus, we see
that the main interpretive issues have been settled, but the philosophical
issues remain as part of Descartes’ legacy to us.
Reference:
1. Cottingham,
John and Robert Stoothoff & Dugald Murdoch: The Philosophical
Writings of Descartes, Cambridge University Press, 1984, Vol.-II,
p.p.-16-17.
2. Descartes,
Rene: Replies to the Second set of Objections in the
Decartes, A collection of critical essays. Edited by Willis Doney,
Anchor Books, Double Day & Company Inc., New York, 1967, p-90.
3. Hintikka,
Jaakko: Cogito, Ergo Sum Inference or Performance; In Descartes:
A Collection of Critical Essays, Edited by Willis Doney, Anchor Books,
Double Day & Company Inc., New York, 1967, p-122.
4. Ibid,
p-123.
5. Markie,
Peter: The Cogito and Its importance; In The Cambridge
Companion to Descartes, Edited by John Cottingham, Cambridge
University Press, 1992, p.p.-145-146.
6. Cottingham,
John and Robert Stoothoff & Dugald Murdoch: The Philosophical
Writings of Descartes, Cambridge University Press, 1984, Vol.-I, p.-127.
7. Ibid,
p.-195
8. Ayer,
A.J.: ‘I Think, Therefore I Am’, In Descartes: A Collection of Critical
Essays, Edited by Willis Doney, Anchor Books, New York, p-82.
No comments :
Post a Comment
We welcome your comments related to the article and the topic being discussed. We expect the comments to be courteous, and respectful of the author and other commenters. Setu reserves the right to moderate, remove or reject comments that contain foul language, insult, hatred, personal information or indicate bad intention. The views expressed in comments reflect those of the commenter, not the official views of the Setu editorial board. рдк्рд░рдХाрд╢िрдд рд░рдЪрдиा рд╕े рд╕рдо्рдмंрдзिрдд рд╢ाрд▓ीрди рд╕рдо्рд╡ाрдж рдХा рд╕्рд╡ाрдЧрдд рд╣ै।